Judge Jyotsna Yagnik’s invocation of
human dignity while not awarding the death penalty in the Naroda-Patiya
massacre case and the Supreme Court’s expression of helplessness while
confirming the death penalty of Ajmal Kasab — sentenced in the 26/11 terror
attack — go to the heart of the constitutional unviability of the death
penalty. We would struggle to make any meaningful distinction in the culpability
we attach to these two crimes but our collective response, in terms of the
punishment they must receive, has been qualitatively different. While it will
be debated whether it was appropriate for a trial judge to invoke concerns of
human dignity at the sentencing stage, judge Yagnik’s judgment has also
inadvertently demonstrated the inherent unfairness of the death penalty. One
can’t help wonder about Kasab’s fate if he had appeared before judge Yagnik
rather than judge M.L. Tahiliani. And it is precisely that unpredictability and
inconsistency in the judicial administration of the death penalty that is at
the heart of the principled objections to the death penalty.
DIFFERENT RESPONSES
There has been very little discussion on
why principled arguments against the death penalty should not apply in Kasab’s
case. Raju Ramachandran, the amicusin Kasab’s case, did a terrific
job in attempting to get the Supreme Court to commute Kasab’s death sentence
but there has been very little else. As a nation and a society we seem to have
quietly accepted the death penalty for Kasab despite all the objections that
have been raised about the death penalty in the past. Kasab’s case is a
significant setback for the move towards complete abolition of the death
penalty in India. It was, in many ways, the perfect case for the death penalty.
A profoundly hurt and grieving society, the guilt of the accused established
through damning photographs and videos, wounded nationalism and the possible
involvement of state actors across the border all contributed towards making
Kasab’s case a strong validation of the need for the death penalty. It is as
though we are acknowledging that there will be moments in our life as a nation
where we will need to satisfy our need for collective revenge. A need satisfied
with the gloss of the rule of law.
On what basis, then, do we not demand the
death penalty for those who masterminded and led the carnage in Naroda-Patiya? Maya Kodnani as an MLA was supposed to represent and
protect the interests of those in her constituency and not lead a mob of
genocidaires to torture, rape and kill many helpless Muslims. Despite that, our
acceptability of the punishments handed down in the Kasab and the Naroda-Patiya
cases has proceeded along very different lines. There will certainly be no
sustained demand for the death penalty for Maya Kodnani and Babu Bajrangi but
there is widespread satisfaction at the confirmation of death penalty for
Kasab. That this qualitative difference in our perception of the two crimes has
found reflection in the judicial administration of the death penalty is most
unfortunate with the invocation of human dignity in one case and no meaningful
engagement with it in another.
The issue is not whether the death
penalty offends human dignity or not. As a polity, we have unfortunately
decided that it does not. The primary issue is whether it is possible to
develop a model of administering the death penalty that is consistent and
non-arbitrary. Judge Yagnik chose not to impose the death penalty because of
her commitment to the position that the human dignity of all convicts must be
respected. Judge Tahiliani either does not subscribe to that view or believes
that it is inappropriate for a trial judge to take such considerations into
account. Either way, it exposes why the ‘rarest of the rare’ framework cannot
work in a fair and consistent manner. It ultimately leaves significant scope
for judicial discretion where all sorts of factors creep in, and has ensured
that comparing the death penalty in India to a lottery would not be an
exaggeration. An analysis of death penalty cases in India from 1950-2006 by
Amnesty International confirms that administering the death penalty has been an
arbitrary exercise. Essentially, it was observed that in many similar
circumstances some convicts were awarded the death penalty and others were not.
In the pursuit of consistent application
of the death penalty, is the solution then to completely remove judicial
discretion? Should we develop a list of very specific crimes where the death
penalty is automatically awarded? Before it was found to be unconstitutional,
Section 303 of the Indian Penal Code provided that an individual who committed
murder while serving a life sentence would be automatically sentenced to death.
Emphasising the importance of individual sentencing, five judges of the Supreme Court in Mithu v. State of Punjab found the automatic sentencing to
be arbitrary and unjust. The inability of the sentencing judges to take into
consideration individual circumstances while deciding the sentence, the judges
felt, would cause grave injustice to the accused.
Achieving a balance between judicial
discretion and individualised sentencing has proved to be an impossible task.
The Supreme Court has tried to address this by developing guidelines in cases
like Bachan Singh and Santosh Bariyar
Case without much success. A damning
indictment of such attempts has been the recent appeal by 14 eminent judges to
the President to commute the death sentence of 13 convicts.
It is stated in the appeal that the
Supreme Court itself has admitted to the wrongful administration of the death
penalty in these 13 cases and that it would be a grave miscarriage of justice
to not commute their sentence. It is time for the Supreme Court to recognise that
it is attempting the impossible by trying to achieve a consistent application
of the death penalty while maintaining the discretion of judges.
This debate between consistent
application of the death penalty and individualised sentencing was at its peak
in the U.S. Supreme Court in the 1970s. In Furman v. Georgia (1972),
the U.S. Supreme Court raised constitutional concerns about the discriminatory
and arbitrary use of the death penalty. After the judgment in Furman,
many States responded with new guidelines for imposing the death penalty,
including some mandatory death penalty schemes. While the attempt of the States
to provide guidelines was upheld, the mandatory death penalty schemes were
struck down in Gregg v. Georgia in 1976. However, the U.S.
experience with ‘guided discretion’ since then has been disastrous and has been
documented in great detail by the Steiker Report (2009) commissioned by the
American Law Institute (ALI).
‘TINKERING WITH THE MACHINERY’
The ALI’s model framework for the
administration of death penalty developed in 1962 provided the basis for the
death penalty statutes that the U.S. Supreme Court found acceptable in Gregg.
However, after the Steiker Report came to the conclusion that the death penalty
continued to be administered in an arbitrary manner, the ALI deleted the death
penalty provisions from its Model Penal Code in December 2009 with no proposal
to introduce another framework. Justice Harry Blackmun’s judicial view on the
death penalty while on the Supreme Court holds an important lesson for India’s
judges in the Supreme Court. Appointed by President Nixon, he started out
upholding the constitutionality of the death penalty including mandatory death
sentences in the 1970s. Until a few months before his retirement in August
1994, Justice Blackmun was a supporter of the death penalty by upholding many
attempts to achieve its non-arbitrary application. But in Callins v.
Collins in February 1994, Justice Blackmun concluded that efforts of
the U.S. Supreme Court over two decades since Furman to ensure
fair and non-arbitrary application of the death penalty had proved to be
futile. Finding the death penalty to be ‘fraught with arbitrariness,
discrimination, caprice, and mistake’, Justice Blackmun revoked his support for
the death penalty by declaring that he would no longer ‘tinker with the
machinery of death’. The Indian Supreme Court must recognise the impossibility
of what it is trying to achieve.
(Anup Surendranath is an Assistant Professor of Law at the
National Law University, Delhi, and a doctoral candidate at the Faculty of Law,
University of Oxford.)
No comments:
Post a Comment